Canadians hardly needed reminding that the Supreme Court’s June 9 decision to strike down the Quebec prohibition on private health insurance for publicly insured services was a landmark judgment. The reactions were many, fulsome, and all over the policy map. Americans, however, heard almost nothing of the contro- versy, hardly surprising given the imbalance between north- ward and southward flows of news.
For critics of Canada’s medicare, the narrow 4-3 deci- sion was judicial confirmation of the program’s overall fail- ure to provide timely and proper access to care. For medicare’s supporters, the decision represented a threat to its core values, especially the principle that access to care should not vary with one’s willingness and ability to pay for private health insurance coverage.
For external observers such as me, (a US academic teaching in Canada), the decision was remarkable for two key reasons. It illustrates vigorous judicial intervention in a political and policy field usually reserved to legislatures. And, at the same time, the court’s majority relied on extraordinarily odd reasoning to justify its position that access to care was so unsatisfactory in Quebec that the ban on private insurance for publicly covered services violated Quebec’s charter of rights. Neither ”œtheory [n]or common sense” provided the majority’s justification. Rather, they claimed, ”œevidence” about how other industrial democra- cies organize their financing of medical care provided their ”œempirical” grounds. Whether the court has any special competence in evaluating the performance of health sys- tems is a serious, deeper question that warrants (and has received) attention.
For decades, Canada’s form of governmentally financed health insurance has been unusual in its ban on supplementary coverage. For leaders like Alberta’s Ralph Klein, who have long argued for more private financing and provision of medical care, the Supreme Court’s deci- sion prompted his immediate approval. ”œAny change that gives Canadians more choice in accessing health care,” he stated on June 9, was worthy. The president of the Canadian Medical Association, Dr. Albert J. Schumacher, described the Court’s ruling as ”œhis- torical,” one that ”œcould substantially change the very foundations of medicare as we know it.” For those like former Saskatchewan premier Roy Romanow who have long celebrated medicare, the decision is a call to action. After all, the court did not hold that the ban was unconstitution- al itself. Instead, it argued that the ”œprohibition on obtaining private health insurance is not constitutional where the public system fails to deliv- er reasonable services.”
The very narrowness of the deci- sion’s grounds is crucial to making sense of the immediate response to the decision: the fear medicare defenders felt, the delight critics expressed, and the policy implications imagined. There was little doubt that private health insurance would be soon for sale in Quebec. But it seemed just as certain that in other provinces, the decision would prompt governmental attention to waiting list problems on the scale of Quebec’s in recent years. In that respect, the decision to my mind war- ranted less celebration from privatizers and justified less fear from defenders of medicare. Understood symbolically, it was easy to understand why the ide- ological stakes initially seemed so high on both sides.
How the Supreme Court made use of evidence from other systems of pub- licly financed medical care is both complicated, flawed and ironic. The experience of other countries with supplementary insurance, the majority contended, ”œrefutes the government’s theory that a prohibition on private health insurance is connected to main- taining quality public health care.” The court went on to state that ”œit does not appear that private participation leads to the eventual demise of public health care.”
Both of these factual claims are true. Every Western European country with universal or near-universal health insurance does permit private financing of care. Nor has any of those countries experienced the ”œdemise” of its public financing in the past decades. But what strikes the outside policy analyst is the peculiarity ”” indeed perversity ”” of the reasoning the court used. Why would anyone sensibly defend the Canadian ban on supplementary cover- age because, otherwise, public programs debase quality or suffer demise?
The real justification of the ban on supplementary health insurance is egalitarian and prudential. Parallel financing, ample research has shown, increases overall costs. Moreover, the experience of private supplementary insurance in Europe is that parallel financing persistently raises questions of fairness. They are a never-ending source of complaint, as illustrated by the controversies over pay beds in British NHS hospitals, private insur- ance coverage of co-payments in France, and the exiting from the pub- lic insurance ”œpool” of those in Germany’s top 10 percent of income earners. Those features are known to the scholars of health care but they were not what the judges noted. The findings suggest prudent lessons from other countries, not stories of policy collapse from supplementary cover- age. Evaluating Canada’s ban involves matters of judgment about what is fair and less costly, not what is simply pos- sible to do.
It may be that the problem of the Chaoulli case for medicare defend- ers was the argumentation the gov- ernment’s lawyers’ offered, not the merits of the case for banning supple- mentary coverage. To the extent the government justified their defense by threats of medicare’s demise or its loss of quality, they made a serious mis- take. There was and is no reason to believe that parallel systems cannot maintain decent quality or survive in recognizable form. The UK has had queue jumping through private insur- ance since 1948, but the NHS remains primarily a place where care is free at the point of service and the over- whelming proportion of the popula- tion relies on it for care. That the British government is today tying to ”œpurchase” care from private suppli- ers from Europe and the United States is itself worthy of attention. The offi- cial justification of that policy is the attempt to reduce the capacity of the privately insured to gain unfair advantage. More access on NHS med- ical grounds will, according to this view, reduce the ability of the wealthi- er to ”œjump the queue.”
The central policy point to make about parallel health insurance is rather simple. Such systems are likely to be more expensive overall, are cer- tain to be less fair, and will not by themselves do very much at all about the length of waiting lists. After all, if Dr. Chaoulli serves a privately financed patient at one time, he can- not at the same time treat a publicly financed one. This point, so obvious to the outsider, prompted less immediate attention than one would have expect- ed. Put differently, one cannot coher- ently claim to be green and white all over at the same time.
The irony is that a controversial, flawed and limited court decision might may well prompt some very desirable results. Those would be remedial legislative action in some jurisdictions (to avoid the decision’s implications) and, more generally, greater intellectual clarity about why restricting private coverage expressed firm and important Cana- dian beliefs about how access to care ought to be shared out. If that were to occur, the Supreme Court’s deci- sion would be a landmark one in a quite different sense.
In the days following the decision, there was a deluge of commentary among critics, defenders, and explica- tors of the court’s decision. Those com- mentaries prompted further attention to two questions: One, why introducing private funding and delivery might not reduce waiting lines (and times)? And, two: precisely what was wrong with the court’s interpretation of the comparative ”œevidence” on which they relied? The answer to the first question is that, in the short run, the supply of caregivers is largely fixed. That means private financing will redistribute attention to some over others, not increase the availability of care itself. The court, as François Béland has noted, did not take on the question of how less waiting time for patients like Zeliotis would fail to increase the wait- ing time of others. The majority decid- ed that the burden of proof was not on the plaintiffs to show that private insurance ”œcures” the waiting list prob- lem. And, as Béland puts it, the court ”œcompletely avoid[ed] examining the possibility that introducing private insurance would lengthen waiting lists in the public sector.”
What was wrong with the major- ity’s treatment of comparative evidence would require an additional essay. As it happens, I provided testi- mony to the trial court about what comparative health policy evidence there was on this topic. So, let me sim- ply repeat what I wrote in conclusion, which directly contradicts the majori- ty’s claims and was cited by the dis- senters. ”œDoubts about the plaintiff’s assumptions are not only based on theoretical problems with the argu- ment that an ”˜exit of anyone from public insurance waiting lists must improve the chances to get care for Canadians left on those lists…’ There is considerable empirical evidence for such skepticism. Real world demon- strations…[show] what might well occur in Canada…In France, for example, there is continuous dispute about the role of cost-sharing by patients in restraining demand for services in a fair and effective way. The result there [has been] less reduction of medical care used (whether justified or not) but the substitution of one source of payment for another. This multiplica- tion of sources of finance weakens rather than strengthens the capacity of a society to decide democratically what health care its citizens should be entitled to and how scarcity should be apportioned.”
The court’s majority posed the wrong questions when dealing with comparative evidence and thus was unable to reject the twin arguments that parallel systems increase costs and allocate access to care unfairly, if that means using ability and willing- ness to pay as criteria of access. What is even more puzzling is that the court’s majority was willing to reject the decisions and grounds of two Quebec courts in a major case that but for one vote would have gone the other way. One ought to be concerned with this kind of judicial expansion.